Reading Time: 2 minutes (906 words)

CHAPTER II SOCIALISM

§ 1 the State and Economic Activity

Socialism aims to transfer control of production from private owners to the State, which would manage all economic activities. This change does not require following strict legal steps usually used for property transfers, as the focus is on who has power over resources. When the State takes more control over production, individual ownership can become meaningless, leaving owners with just a title.

Anarchism believes that every form of coercion, including the State, is unnecessary and that society can thrive without it. Anarchists think people can work together without force. In contrast, liberals accept a legal system that limits State power and support private ownership, while socialists want the State to have more control to benefit the public. Both ideologies have different views on the role of the State but aim to improve society through different methods.

§ 2 the ‘Fundamental Rights’ of Socialist Theory

The discussion focuses on the fundamental rights within socialist theory, contrasting them with liberal rights that emerged during the 18th and 19th centuries. Liberal philosophy promoted natural rights, known as the Rights of Man and Citizens, but these rights often became more of a political agenda rather than practical laws. The inclusion of such rights in constitutions has led to limited actual freedom for citizens. For instance, while Austria's fundamental law allows freedom of expression, there are so many legal restrictions that it fails in practice. In contrast, England, though lacking a formal fundamental right for free expression, has a society where such freedoms thrive due to the overall legal atmosphere.

In response to liberal rights, some criticize their insufficiency and seek basic economic rights as principles needed for a fair society. These rights serve as critiques of current social structures. Notably, Anton Menger identifies three fundamental economic rights in socialism: the right to the full produce of labor, the right to existence, and the right to work. Each of these highlights various disparities within the existing economic system.

The right to the full produce of labor advocates that workers should receive the total value of what they produce. However, assessing how much labor contributes to production is complex and often subjective. Critics argue that claiming the full product of labor as a right is unrealistic because it overlooks the role of capital and land in production. Ultimately, this idea becomes more of a slogan calling for the elimination of income that isn't derived from labor.

The right to existence demands that individuals, especially those unable to work, have access to basic necessities. It suggests a more equitable distribution of goods, asserting that everyone's essential needs should be met before considering others’ less urgent desires. Yet, achieving this right likely requires socializing the means of production, which would allow the state to manage and distribute resources based on collective needs.

Lastly, the right to work underscores the duty of society to provide jobs to all. In socialist interpretation, this transforms into a claim that individuals should receive work suited to their abilities that also ensures their subsistence. However, this idea is seen as flawed because it assumes that a natural state of sufficiency existed before society's influence, ignoring the realities of economic needs and the market dynamics.

Overall, these economic rights represent outdated ideals of social reform, overshadowed by the broader goal of socializing production to address the underlying economic disparities.

§ 3 Collectivism and Socialism

There's a big debate in philosophy about whether we should focus on the group or the individual. We call these ideas "collectivism" and "individualism." Collectivists think about society like a team where everyone works together for a common goal, even if it means some personal sacrifice. They see groups, like nations or social classes, as really powerful forces. Individualists, on the other hand, believe that individuals are most important and that society works best when everyone is free to pursue their own goals. They think groups are just collections of individuals, not some super-powerful entity.

Collectivists sometimes use their ideas to justify those in power. They might say, for example, that everyone needs to follow the leader without question because it's good for the nation. Individualists criticize this, arguing that it leads to those in charge taking advantage of everyone else. They think society works better when everyone's voice can be heard.

Individualism became really important during the Enlightenment. Thinkers started to say that maybe people could get along and build a good society without a powerful ruler forcing them to. They believed that when people cooperate freely, everyone benefits. This idea had a big impact on economics and political theory.

However, collectivism never really went away. Some people really like the idea of belonging to a powerful group. They might be really patriotic, for example, or devoted to a particular cause. This kind of collectivism is about emotion and belonging, not so much about logic and reason.

One of the big problems with collectivism is that it struggles to explain how a group develops a single "will." They'll talk about "the will of the people," but people disagree all the time! How can a group have one single desire? This is where collectivism gets fuzzy. Individualism has an easier time here: people have their own individual desires, and they act on them.

Overall, collectivism is based more on political ideals than scientific thinking. It's about how people think society *should* work, not necessarily how it actually *does* work. It often relies on vague ideas about the group, while individualism is more focused on the individual and their choices.